Ranking 24 Aug 2010 A diversion in the natural classification series. In natural classification, we typically do not find that patterns due to the process of historical causation come arrayed neatly in boxes within boxes, and yet one of the most common temptations is for classifiers to set up fixed ranks. The Linnaean scheme of classification for animals, plants and minerals famously set up a number (initially five) of ranks, with the “Empire of Nature”, divided into “kingdoms”, “orders”, “classes”, “genera”, and “species”. Later, “families” were added, and then “phyla” (among animals) and “divisions (for plants). By the end of the nineteenth century, however, there had been a constant division of ranks into “super-” and “infra-” ranks, and new ranks such as “tribes” were added. Ranked classifications for minerals, however, were abandoned fairly soon after Linnaeus, and was replaced by the scheme of “metamorphic, igneous and sedimentary” rocks (a process-based classification) and the later scheme for minerals based on chemical composition (which will be discussed later). However, Linnaeus himself did not take his ranks seriously, or not as seriously as those who followed him, including Darwin and many of the post-Darwin evolutionists, right up to the Modern Synthesis in the period 1940-1970. “The species and the genus”, he wrote, “are always the work of nature; the variety mostly of cultivation; the class and the order [are the work] of nature and art.”* In contrast, even Darwin tried to come up with laws of the speciation rates of higher taxa on the understanding they were real things in themselves. When people assert blithely that Darwin did not believe in the reality of species, they appeal to the following text (Origin of Species, 5th edition used): Certainly no clear line of demarcation has as yet been drawn between species and sub-species – that is, the forms which in the opinion of some naturalists come very near to, but do not quite arrive at, the rank of species: or, again, between sub-species and well-marked varieties, or between lesser varieties and individual differences. These differences blend into each other by an insensible series; and a series impresses the mind with the idea of an actual passage. [p44f] From these remarks it will be seen that I look at the term species as one arbitrarily given, for the sake of convenience, to a set of individuals closely resembling each other, and that it does not essentially differ from the term variety, which is given to less distinct and more fluctuating forms. The term variety, again, in comparison with mere individual differences, is also applied arbitrarily, for convenience’ sake. [p46] But here we see Darwin denying not the reality of the species, but of the rank of species (which Ernst Mayr incorrectly called the “species category”). Darwin holds that organisms fade from varieties to species and above. This sort of rank nominalism is very different from species “nominalism” (or better, species denialism; since there is no sense in which the species are nominal essences). Ranking is one of those classificatory activities we feel obliged to undertake, and once we have done so, we also feel obliged to defend as natural, but this cannot be so. There are no reasons to think higher taxa are real ranks, although the things we rank can be. For example, the rank of “phylum” is arbitrary and depends solely on what we, as observers, take to be salient differences. But the phyla we name, such as “Chordata”, are real entities if they are formed by monophyletic relations. It’s just that you cannot compare one with another (bacterial phyla are a case in point: you cannot compare Chrysogenetes with one species, with Xenobacteria, with 26, let alone with, say, Annelida (worms), with 16 thousand and more. What makes a phylum (or, in plants, a Division)? Basically it’s that some systematist with authority has declared that it doesn’t resemble some other group “enough”. The declaration of a phylum is a joint fact: it depends on facts about the groups themselves, but also on facts about what impresses systematists. In work done by Scott Atran and others (Atran 1995, 1998, 1999; Sousa et al 2002; Berlin 1973, 1976; Berlin et al 1973), it appears that we have a tendency to rank things at or around 5 to 7 levels (see figure). This melds nicely with Linnaeus’s initial ranking scheme of five, which was later extended to include family and phylum (division) before the rank explosion of the mid-19th century. This is a psychologistic fact, a fact about us. It is not the foundation for inferences about nature, but for inferences about the psychology, politics and social structure of science. From Berlin et al, 1973: 215. * “NATURAE opus semper est Species Genus: CULTURAE saepius Varietas; NATURAE & ARTIS Classis & Ordo.”, Carolus Linnaeus, Philosophia Botanica (1751), aphorism 162. Trans. Franz A. Stafleu. 1971. Linnaeus and the Linnaeans. The spreading of their ideas in systematic botany, 1735-1789, Regnum vegetabile, v. 79. Utrecht: Oosthoek, 67, modified by me. References Atran, Scott. 1995. Causal constraints on categories and categorical constraints on biological reasoning across cultures. In Causal cognition: a multidisciplinary debate, edited by D. Sperber, D. Premack and A. J. Premack. Oxford, UK: New York: Clarendon Press; Oxford University Press:205–223. ———. 1998. Folk biology and the anthropology of science: cognitive universals and the cultural particulars. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (4):547–609. ———. 1999. The universal primacy of generic species in folkbiological taxonomy: Implications for human biological, cultural and scientific evolution. In Species, New interdisciplinary essays, edited by R. A. Wilson. Cambridge, MA: Bradford/MIT Press:231-261. Berlin, Brent. 1973. Folk Systematics in Relation to Biological Classification and Nomenclature. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 4 (1):259-271. –––. 1976. The concept of rank in ethnobiological classification: Some evidence from Aguaruna folk botany. American Ethnologist 3 (3):381-399. Berlin, Brent, Dennis E. Breedlove, and Peter H. Raven. 1973. General Principles of Classification and Nomenclature in Folk Biology. American Anthropologist 75 (1):214-242. Sousa, Paulo, Scott Atran, and Douglas Medin. 2002. Essentialism and Folkbiology: Evidence from Brazil. Journal of Cognition and Culture 2 (3):195. Biology Epistemology General Science Natural Classification Philosophy Science Species and systematics Systematics Natural ClassificationPhilosophy
Administrative Lazy Manager Theory 18 Nov 2009 Some people have asked me how I did a PhD, and wrote and taught a subject, while I was also manager of a department of graphic artists, receptionists, and animators, and did the annual report and various other publications. The answer is: Lazy Manager Theory The principle is: if you… Read More
Evolution On the problem of the problem of evil and Darwin 15 Mar 2011 In yet another essay reprising his argument that theists can be good Darwinians (a position I concur with, incidentally), Michael Ruse makes the following comment, based on a book by Karl Giberson and Francis Collins, The Language of Science and Faith: Straight Answers to Genuine Questions: Where I do want… Read More
Cognition Analytic thinking, religion and science – the rhetoric and the psychology 5 May 20125 May 2012 Over the past few decades there has been an increasingly large literature on styles of thinking and cognitive biases (to which I am grateful to Jocelyn Stoller, a reader of this blog, for introducing me) in psychology, culminating in the marvellous book, which I recommend to everyone, by Daniel Kahneman, Thinking… Read More
I expect you are already familiar with “Miller’s Law” from the famous paper “The Magical Number Seven, Plus or Minus Two: Some Limits on Our Capacity for Processing Information”. Abraham Maslow had some thoughts about how we separate people into boxes: “Rubricizing is a cheap form of cognizing, i.e., really a form of not-cognizing, a quick, easy cataloguing whose function is to make unnecessary the effort required by more careful, idiographic perceiving or thinking. To place a person in a system takes less energy than to know him in his own right, since in the former instance, all that has to be perceived is that one abstracted characteristic which indicates his belongingness in a class.” I’ve come to the conclusion that our cognitive biases lead us into making similar events into an object, and categorizing many objects into a small number of pigeon holes. It’s probably an evolutionary kludge for dealing with a complex life in a simple (and mostly effective enough) way. All of which is probably why we get in such a tangle trying to define ‘species’ or some classification scheme. We could do with a better metaphor to think with… perhaps with computer assistance.
“Mid-nineteenth-century rank explosion”? I thought phylum (stem) was added in the 1860s, and the super- and sub-ranks were only conceived in the late 19th century. Umph … shows you what I know. Is this rank explosion pre- or post-Origin?
“A phylum is a species that’s been evolving for 6oo million years.” attrib. – any number of people fusilier James 2:24
Where was PhyloCode mentioned? It is illogical to assume that opposition to ranks or recognition of the illogical nature of ranks indicates support of PhyloCode.
Where did I suggest what you are claiming I did. I just don’t understand PhyloCode and Mr. Wilkins seems like the person who could explain it to me. I regard that as a compliment to Mr. Wilkins’ skill. The fact that you read into my request only what you want to see will not be taken as complimentary towards you.
Are species individuals? If so, is Chordata an individual. If not, what is magic about species rank? Seems to me that somewhere around this diversion is the time to discuss these questions. If you do intend to discuss them.
I will shortly. The point about Phylocode however is complex. On the one hand, ranks are unreal conventions. On the other, why not use them as Linnaeus suggested, as convenient tools? If they don’t matter, then we can sustain our present practices, abandoning which would be very costly. But neither matters so long as the taxa are real that they name.
My sense is that in Zoology, a Phylum is… as big a group as people in the 20th C were confident of. Arthropoda is a phylum because (a) sure there were sccptics, but bugs, spiders and crabs just LOOK as if they ought to compose a monophyletic group, and (b) what the closest relatives to this group were was utterly mysterious. Nowadays, I guess, Ecdysozoa would be thought about as convincingly demonstrated as Arthropoda was 30 years ago, but A and the smaller Ecdysozoan groups got labeled as Phyla when that wasn’t so. … Not that that gets it quite right (I think most zoologists wouold have agreed in 1980 or 1960 that Chordata+Hemichordata+Echinodermata was a clade, but the three are counted as separate Phyla. Maybe because Chordata and Echinodermata had been named as Phyla earlier, when they were maximal well-supported clades? … General picture: in some area (Mammals, Vertebrates, Animals…) some big groupings that seem pretty clearly monophyletic get named and assigned the highest rank (Order, Class, Phylum…) available for subgroups of the area. And then the odds and sods that nobody knows how to connect to anything else get assigned to a bunch of small groups of the same rank.
I think you are right. This is a psychologistic point: a phylum (or order, family, genus and tribe, etc.) is a group that roughly look as similar to each other as members of equivalent “levels” are, a point that tells us a lot about the observational dispositions of the classifiers.